Table of Contents

PBA310Y: The Good Samaritan Argument (The Violinist)

Prerequisite: PBA210H

FIXME clip from movie Up for Killing Versus Letting Die FIXME story of gas station, kid getting into wrong car and guy driving away, for Guarding argument thing

Judith Jarvis Thompson

Analysis

Themes

Thomson doesn't actually believe a pre-born child is a person, even though she tries to assume the premise.2)

Bizarre Language

Commentary

David Boonin: The Good Samaritan Argument

From the moral point of view, that is, a woman who carries a pregnancy to term is like a person who generously offers at some considerable cost to herself to provide waht another needs but does not have the right to, while a woman who declines to carry a pregnancy to term is like a person who declines to offer such assistance. It is not the case that abortion violates the requirements of morality, on this account, but rather that continuing to incur the burdens involved in a typical pregnancy goes beyond them, even if the fetus does have the same right to life that you or I have. […] while I will not attempt to defend Thomson's defense of the good samaritan argument, I will attempt to defend the argument itself.3)

Boonin summarizes Thompson's framing of the pro-life argument4):

Thomson presents this scenario in response:

You wake up in the morning and find yourself back to back in bed with an unconscious violinist. A famous unconscious violinist. He has been found to have a fatal kidney ailment, and the Society of Music Lovers has canvassed all the available medical records and found that you alone have the right blood type to help. They have therefore kidnapped you, and last night the violinist's circulatory system was plugged into yours, so that your kidneys can be used to extract poisons from his blood as well as your own. The director of the hospital now tells you, “Look, we're sorry the Society of Music Lovers did this to you – we would never have permitted it if we had known. But still, they did it, and the violinist is now plugged into you. To unplug you would be to kill him. But never mind, it's only for nine months. By then he will have recovered from his ailment, and can safely be unplugged from you.” (1971: 132)

Boonin claims she's not attacking P4, as many claim. Surely Thomson would agree the right to control your body doesn't trump a right to life when they are in genuine conflict, e.g. the right to swing your fists and pummel someone else to death.5) She is not arguing that the right to control your body outweighs someone else's right to life. Thomson's claim is that there's no such conflict in the first place, that a right to life does not entail a right to use your kidneys. “So, in unplugging yourself from him, you do nothing that conflicts with his right to life, even though you do something that brings about his death. […] the fetus's right to life does not include or entail the right to be provided with the use or the continued use of whatever is needed in order for it to go on living.”6)

Thomson is arguing that C2 does not follow without P6, and that P6 is not true. “The right to life does not include or entail the right to life support.”7) Thomson says, “We need to be shown also that killing the foetus violates its right to life, i.e., that abortion is unjust killing. And is it?”8)

However, you still need to show that if P6 is false for unplugging the violinist, that it's also false for abortion – that the two cases are sufficiently analogous. Boonin says Thomson's argument is that the rights-based argument against abortion is unsuccessful without P6, and that it cannot be revised to succeed with P6.

The Weirdness Objection

Objections on the Way in Which the Relationship Begins

There is at least one obvious difference between the two cases that seems plainly to be of moral significance. In the case of you and the violinist, the situation in which you find that there is a violinist whose life is dependent on you does not arise from any voluntary action of yours. But when a woman becomes pregnant, except in cases where the pregnancy arises from rape, the situation in which she finds that there is a fetus whose life is dependent on her does arise, at least in part, from a voluntary action of hers. If she had not voluntarily engaged in sexual intercourse, she would not have become pregnant.12)

Thomson provided an initial reply to this objection:

I suppose we may take it as a datum that in a case of pregnancy due to rape the mother has not given the unborn person a right to the use of her body for food and shelter. Indeed, in what pregnancy could it be supposed that the mother has given the unborn person such a right? It is not as if there were unborn persons drifting about the world, to whom a woman who wants a child says “I invite you in.”13)

Boonin believes Thomson's response to this objection rests on the following two claims14):

  1. the fetus cannot acquire the right to use the woman's body unless we can suppose that the woman has given the fetus this right
    • The Responsibility Objection: “a person can acquire the right to your assistance when his need for your assistance (foreseeably) arises from a voluntary action of yours on the grounds that you are responsible for his state of need, even if in doing the action that led to his being in a state of need you did not 'give' him the right to your assistance either explicitly or tacitly.”, e.g. a hunter's responsibility towards an innocent bystander he has accidentally shot. “Because the woman in nonrape cases is responsible for the fact that there is a fetus whose life now depends on the use of her body in order to survive, the fetus has acquired a right to the use of her body even if the woman has not 'given' this right to the fetus, explicitly or otherwise”
  2. we cannot suppose that the woman has given the fetus this right unless she has explicitly agreed to do so
    • The Tacit Consent Objection: “because the woman's pregnancy in nonrape cases is the (foreseeable) result of a voluntary action of hers, she should be understood as having tacitly” consented

Boonin finds Thomson's replies/sidestepping to these objections entirely unsatisfactory. For example, what about people who fail to use contraception? Or what about the fact that contraceptive methods are known to be imperfect? 15) “A hunter, for example, can plausibly be held responsible for taking care of an innocent bystander she accidentally shoots, even if she takes every reasonable precaution to avoid such an accident short of not going hunting in the first place.” 16)

Boonin believes that although Thomson's responses fail, that sufficient refutations to these objections can be given.17)

(Interestingly, Boonin remarks that pro-lifers who support abortion in the case of rape have a problem of being inconsistent, but taking the Good Samaritan Argument but limited to cases of rape only would solve this inconsistency – and in this way be a greater contribution to rape-exception abortion critics than abortion advocates.18) His claim that “a significant portion of those who generally oppose abortion are willing to make an exception in [cases of rape]” seems either too focused on the American political context, or on the mushy middle that pro-life activists are trying to change anyways.)

  1. Because the woman's act of intercourse is voluntary, she should be understood as having tacitly consented to something with respect to the state of affairs in which there is now a fetus developing inside of her body
    • Boonin says this confuses (a) voluntarily bringing about a certain state of affairs with (b) voluntarily doing an action foreseeing that this may lead to a certain state of affairs – and that only (a) is plausible for grounding tacit consent, yet only (b) is applicable to nonrape pregnancy cases19)
    • Boonin asks what would you have to believe about tacit consent for this objection to hold, which Boonin says may well be necessary but are not sufficient:
      • voluntary action
      • causal relationship between action and resulting state of affairs
      • Foreseeable (if unintended) consequence
    • Boonin's example to try to prove the distinction between (a) and (b)20)
      • Bill and Ted both leave a restaurant after voluntarily placing some cash on the table
      • But Bill placed the money there for the waiter (a)
      • Ted simply was uncomfortable with the cash in his pocket, placed it on the table temporarily, intending to put most of it back into his pocked, knowing he might forget it, did not take precautions (e.g. tying a string to his finger) to remember and didn't remember until 10 minutes after leaving the restaurant – at which point he returns to try to get most of his money back. This is (b) because Bill voluntarily took an action foreseeing that it might bring about a state of affairs, but did not voluntarily bring about that state of affairs.
      • Boonin says it would be unreasonable to say that Ted tacitly consented to the waiter taking all of his cash – the voluntariness, causality and foreseeability are not sufficient for tacit consent. (One might say that Ted is nonetheless responsible or that his actions were negligent, but then this is the responsibility argument, not the tacit consent argument.)
      • Boonin says a woman who has sex knowing it might lead to pregnancy is like Ted, not Bill. Just as Ted's returning to the restaurant is evidence that he never tacitly consented to giving away the whole pile of cash, a woman's procuring an abortion is evidence that she never tacitly consented to giving her child the right to use her body.21)
      • Furthermore, Boonin later says that we can only assume Bill has tacitly consenting to giving this money to the waiter because of a well-established cultural convention. So, for example in a culture that finds having children out of wedlock morally impermissible yet abortion permissible, what could be assumed about tacit consent to the child through sex would be wildly different and may actually suggest the opposite. “The point is simply that a person's act cannot reasonably be taken as evidence of tacitly consenting to something unless it takes place in a context in which it is generally understood as constituting such consent.”22)
    • Boonin addresses Langer's tacit consent objection, saying that if a woman had voluntarily joined the Society of Music Lovers knowing she'd be entered into a lottery to be plugged into the violinist, that she would have waived her right to control over her body in this way.
      • Boonin says “her voluntary action is the act of agreeing to abide by the society's rules. […] In order for the two cases to be parallel, then, we must assume that [a pregnant] woman has similarly agreed to enter her name in a comparable pregnancy lottery by virtue of her having engaged in voluntary intercourse. BUt we cannot assume that she has so agreed because whether or not she has agreed is precisely the question we are attempting to answer.”23)
        • Blaise: Is that true? Isn't there a relevant question of whether you could agree to have sex with knowledge that having sex is basically entering into a biological pregnancy lottery without agreeing to enter the biological pregnancy lottery? With knowledge, can you eat a piece of cake daily without tacitly consenting to the obesity that might result? With knowledge (and addiction aside), can you smoke a pack of cigarettes a day without tacitly consenting to entering the biological lung cancer lottery? Maybe this isn't a question of tacit consent… but can Boonin really just dismiss the biological pregnancy lottery that is sexual intercourse as irrelevant? How can you have sex, knowing that's where babies come from – knowing those are the biological rules of the game – without agreeing to the rules?
        • I suppose you could if you don't agree to the biological rules because you'll kill any human being that results, but I guess the separate question is whether or not that's morally acceptable to kill another human being because you don't consent to the rules of biology. Is refusing to follow the reality of sexual reproduction grounds for killing another human being?
      • Boonin says, say you knew the Society of Music Lovers kidnappers were lurking in a park and you walked by it anyways taking the risk, without carrying any protection. Surely no one will say you've tacitly consented to remain plugged into the violinist if you're kidnapped
        • Blaise: there seems to be a morally relevant difference in whether or not the reason why you experience an unintended but foreseen consequence that you knowingly risked through your voluntarily actions, if that reason is other people's voluntary and immoral actions to violate your rights, versus if that other reason is basic biological realities. Is it really the same thing to say that you didn't consent to a kidnapping and thus around bound morally versus you didn't consent to get sunburnt when you went outside for 3 hours midday with no sunscreen knowing that's how sunburns happen? While it might be meaningful to say that you did not tacitly consent to being kidnapped, I'm not sure if it's meaningful to say that you didn't tacitly consent to being sunburnt. Though, maybe it is more a question of responsibility than consent, but there is a consent to risk here.
        • Blaise: another way to put it: is the causal effect only your voluntary actions? Or the way others acting on top of your voluntary actions? When the cause of the unintended consequence is your action + biology, that seems radically different than when the cause of the unintended consequence is your action + kidnapping. Is it actually meaningful to say that you did not consent to the state of affairs emerging from the sunburn scenario? That you did not consent to biological realities?
        • Boonin tries to address this by removing the culpable agent and putting the second variable as a Y2K computer bug.24)
          • Blaise: A random computer glitch that brings about a procedure radically different from the one in which you entered the hospital to receive still hardly seems analogous to experiencing the natural and commonplace and hardly surprising outcome of having sexual intercourse. Getting pregnant from sex is not like getting hooked up to the violinist because of a random computer glitch. The random computer glitch seriously calls into question the foreseeability requirement – sure you know it's the eve of Y2K, but it wouldn't be foreseeable that hospital staff would be so negligent as to proceed in the face of the glitch (so, not total inculpability either)
          • Blaise: Even when Boonin tries to rescue this by making the probabilities of randomness exactly equal to the changes of conception in a single sexual act, or maybe adding serious infertility problems to the woman who does actually get pregnant25), the difference of randomness versus natural outcome still remains (and hospital staff proceeding despite the random error). Even at equal odds, sex causing pregnancy has a much stronger foreseeability and causal relationship than a random computer glitch causing hospital staff to give you the wrong operation. You could make the odds equal between getting pregnant from sex and dying from a freak accident (lighting a match causing you to be incinerated from a gas leak, getting struck by a piece of falling ice walking down the street), and it wouldn't make the two situations analogous.
    • Blaise: I'm still not sure that it's soley a question of tacit consent here. But I don't think Boonin successfully dismisses consent entirely, even if it's a tacit consent to assume the risk of pregnancy as a possible outcome of sex rather than consent specifically to the use of your body – perhaps it's some form of consent combined with the responsibility argument
  2. What she should be understood as having tacitly consented to with respect to this state of affairs is, in particular, the fetus's having a right to have the state of affairs continue for as long as this is necessary for it to remain alive
    • “Suppose that the procedure involved in unplugging you from the violinist is itself somewhat painful and costly. […] We might say that freely plugging yourself into the violinist constitutes consent to bear the costs of unplugging yourself. But does it constitute consent to more, and in particular, does it… constitute consent to remain plugged in for the nine-month period that the violinist requires?”26)
      • What if you had to undergo nine painful bone marrow extractions over the next nine months, and you freely volunteer at first without fully understanding what's involved, would you be morally obligated to complete the rest of the extractions if you changed your mind after two?27)
        • Blaise: What if you could only unplug yourself by decapitating the violinist?
        • Blaise: What about ordinary versus extraordinary care? A bone marrow extraction is not analogous to providing food and shelter for a child. What if you agreed to travel with a newborn baby from one location to another, but found it seriously burdensome to continue to carry, feed and shelter the child in the middle of a difficult journey? Since you consenting to the journey, does the child not have a right to your basic support until the journey is over? Or can you leave the child to starve? Or dismember the child to remove yourself from the demands you initially consented to?

The Responsibility Objection

“The woman is like someone whose voluntary actions foreseeably lead to an accident that causes an innocent bystander to be in need of assistance.”29)

“If you had not done the voluntary action, then he would not now need your assistance in order to survive.”32)

  1. existence: If you had not done the act, then he would not now exist (and so would not now need your assistance in order to survive): you are responsible for the fact that the other person now exists
  2. neediness: If you had not done the act, then he would now exist, and would not need your assistance in order to survive: you are responsible for the fact that, given that the other person now exists, he stands in need of your assistance

Boonin wants to accept responsibility #2, but reject responsibility #1. And… well, just read him:

In one important respect, the responsibility objection is correct. Cases of voluntary intercourse are relevantly different from Thomson's example. But in another important respect, the objection is mistaken. Cases of voluntary intercourse are also relevantly different from cases such as those cited by Beckwith, Carrier, and Tooley. In those cases, when you are responsible for the fact that another stands in need of your assistance, you are responsible in sense (2) and not in sense (1). You are responsible for their neediness given that they exists, that is, but you are not responsible for the fact that they exist in the first place. […] If she had not voluntarily had intercourse, the fetus would not now exist. BUt it is not the case that she did some voluntary action such that had she not done it the fetus would now exist and would not need her assistance in order to survive. There was no option available to her on which the fetus would now exist and not be in need of her assistance. […] A woman whose pregnancy arises from voluntary intercourse is responsible for the fetus's existence, but she is not responsible for its neediness, given that it exists.33)

* Blaise: Huh? You're responsible that that existence, but since there's no possible way for a fetus to exist without being in need… you're not responsible for the neediness?? Wouldn't it follow rather that you're responsible for their existence and neediness, because existence and neediness are inseparable at that age for members of our species given our current medical technology? How does the inseparability between existence and neediness here imply that the responsible does not extend to neediness, rather than implying the very opposite – that whoever is responsible for the existence of a fetus is by extension necessarily also responsible for his or her neediness? What kind of insanely backwards hair-splitting is this… If you are responsible for the existence of an inherently needy person – especially where that neediness is natural and foreseeable – are you not also responsible for their need?

Boonin finds it hard to come up with another suitable analogy for creating life, but instead turns to analogies for extending life to test the existence claim

Imperfect Drug34): You are the violinist's doctor. Seven years ago, you discovered that the violinist ahd contracted a rare disease that was on the verge of killing him. The only way to save his life that was available to you was to give him a drug that cures the disease but has one unfortunate side effect: Five to ten years after ingestion, it often causes the kidney ailment described in Thomson's story. Knowing that you alone would have the appropriate blood type to save the violinist were his kidneys to fail, you prescribed the drug and cured the disease. The violinist has now been struck by the kidney ailment. If you do not allow him the use of your kidneys for nine months, he will die.35)

Boonin fumbles on Langer's objection about having a responsibility to care for his one-year-born son when he's only responsible for his existence (voluntary sex) but not necessarily for his neediness (there was no option to procreate and have a non-needy one-year-born child). Boonin says, okay, so maybe sometimes being responsible for someone's existence can make us responsible for their neediness, but that doesn't mean it's always true! Just because it's true for the father of a one-year-born kid doesn't mean it's true for the mother of a kid who's a few months old in the womb. 37)

Then… he jumps the shark: He finds objections to the Imperfect Drug scenario successful, because they don't make the distinction he emphasized against the Tacit Consent Argument, that is the distinct between voluntarily bringing about the state of affairs versus taking voluntary actions through which a state of affairs may arise as a foreseeable unintended consequence39). So the whole imperfect drug thing was an exercise in how not to modify the scenario.

Instead, he suggests this…

Hedonist: You are a hedonist who wishes to engage in a very pleasurable activity. The activity is such that if you engage in it, there is a chance that it will cause some gas to be released that will result in adding a few extra months of unconscious existence to the life of some already-comatose violinist in the world. As things now stand, this violinist has no more conscious life ahead of him. But if the gas is released, and if she does have a few extra months of unconscious life added as a result, it will then become possible for you to bring him out of his coma by giving him the use of your kidneys for nine months. There are certain devices that you can use during the pleasurable activity which reduce the chances of gas emission but do not eliminate them entirely, but you do not like the way the use of such devices “makes you feel” when you engage in the pleasurable activity. So you engage in the pleasurable activity, and without such devices. As a (foreseeable but not intended) result, some gas escapes, causing some extra unconscious time to be added to the life of an already comatose violinist, and making it possible for him to then be brought out of his coma if you remain plugged into him for nine months.

* Blaise: Now I understand why Boonin begins the chapter addressing “The Weirdness Objection.” Seriously. He thinks this is more analogous to pregnancy than Thomson's kidnapping life support machine setup? That the positive externalities of a hedonist's gas emission is like procreation? That the causal relationship between a hedonist's excess gas emission's prolonging the life of someone in a coma are analogous to the causal relationship between sexual intercourse and reproduction? o.O

Based on this scenario (this scenario?!), he concludes that if the good samaritan argument succeeds for rape cases that it also succeeds for nonrape cases. The rest of the chapter is devoted to arguing that it succeeds for rape cases.

FIXME Boonin vs. Trent Horn debate – watch later https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=h3Grc1d2gew

Objections on the Way in Which the Relationship Ends

The Tacit Consent and Responsibility Objection are based around the differences between the relationship between you and the violinist and a pregnant woman and her child. Afterwards, he addresses two other objections, that focus on the difference in the way the relationship ends.

  1. Killing Versus Letting DIe
  2. The Intending Versions Foreseeing Objection

The Killing Versus Letting Die Objection

Do you really think that you are permitted to unplug yourself from the violinist if in order to do so you must first dismember or burn him to death? Two of the most influential rebuttals to THomson's original paper cite this as the single greatest problem with the good samaritan argument.40)

Thomson tries to dismiss the distinction:

Now it had not actually escaped my notice that the mother who aborts herself kills the child, whereas a man who refuses to be a Good Samaritan – on the traditional understanding of Good Samaritan – merely does not save. My suggestion was that from a moral point of view these cases should be assimilated. The woman who allows the pregnancy to continue, at great cost to herself, is entitled to praise in the same amount, and, more important, of the same kind as is the man who sets forth, at great cost to himself, to give aid. That is why I proposed we attend to the case of you and the violinist.41)

* “Thomson's response to the killing versus letting die objection leaves her position vulnerable to those who think that there are sound independent reasons to place great moral weight on the distinction between killing and letting die.”42)

The Intending Versus Foreseeing Objection

FIXME rest of the chapter

De Facto Guardian

FIXME Paper from Justice for all that dives extensively into the De Facto Guardian argument (includes the “Up” analogy, woman in the cabin analogy, etc.) *http://doc.jfaweb.org/Training/DeFactoGuardian-v03.pdf

1)
“Surely we do not have any such “special responsibility” for a person unless we have assumed it, explicitly or implicitly […] they do not simply by virtue of their biological relationship to the child who comes into existence have a special responsibility for it”
2)
“it should be remembered that we have only been pretending throughout that the fetus is a human being from the moment of conception. A very early abortion is surely not the killing of a person, and so is not dealt with by anything I have said here.”
3)
Boonin, p. 133-134.
4)
Boonin, 135
5)
Boonin, 136
6) , 7)
Boonin, 137
8)
1971: 136, 138
9)
Boonin, 139-143
10)
Boonin, 143-146
11)
Boonin, 147
12)
Boonin, 148
13)
Thomson, 138
14)
Boonin, 149
15)
Boonin, 150
16) , 18)
Boonin, 151
17)
Boonin, 188
19)
Boonin, 154
20)
Boonin, 156-157
21)
Boonin, 159
22)
Boonin, 164
23)
Boonin, 161
24)
Boonin, 162
25)
Boonin, 163
26) , 27)
Boonin, 165
28)
Boonin, 166-167
29) , 30)
Boonin, 167
31)
Boonin, 168
32)
Boonin, 169
33)
Boonin, 171
34)
There's also a second, but I don't think the second is necessary to understand the point; and a third, but Boonin just has this bizarre begging the question line of argument where we conveniently drops the presumption that a pre-born child is a person with a right to life in order to suggest that it's begging the question to say it's worse to have been created and then aborted than not to have been created at all
35)
Boonin, 172-173
36)
Boonin, 174-175
37)
Boonin, 180-182
38)
Boonin, 183
39)
Boonin, 186
40)
Boonin, 189
41)
Thomson, 157
42)
Boonin, 190
43)
Boonin, 192
44)
Boonin, 193-194
45)
Boonin, 197